An Analysis of Mendel's Two Hybridist Theories and their Intertheoretical Relationships
- Autores
- Lorenzano, Pablo Julio
- Año de publicación
- 2022
- Idioma
- inglés
- Tipo de recurso
- artículo
- Estado
- versión publicada
- Descripción
- Based on a statistical analysis of his experiments, which was a novelty for the tradition of “horticulturalists” (or “plant breeders”) as well as for the tradition of “hybridists”, and seeking a “generally applicable law governing the formation and development of hybrids” (MENDEL 1865: 3), Mendel states “the law of development/evolution found for Pisum” (MENDEL 1865: 32). When he tries to provide the “foundation and explanation” (MENDEL 1865: 32) of the law of formation and development of hybrids, he does it in terms of the production and behavior of egg cells and pollen cells, and, ultimately, in terms of the nature and behavior of what he calls “elements” (MENDEL 1865: 41) or “cell elements” (MENDEL 1865: 42). Moreover, Mendel recognizes the existence not just of hybrids that behave like those of Pisum – i.e., of “variable hybrids” – but also of hybrids that “remain perfectly like the hybrid and continue constant in their offspring” (MENDEL 1865: 38) and “acquire the status of new species” (MENDEL 1865: 40) – i.e., of “constant hybrids” (MENDEL 1869: 27–28, 31). The law that would govern the behavior of constant hybrids would also find its foundation and explanation in terms of the nature and behavior of elements (or cell elements). Mendel’s hybridism consists of two theories: a theory that moves on a more “empirical” level, according to Schleiden’s first “special guiding maxim”, the “Maxim of the history of development/evolution” (SCHLEIDEN 1849: 141, 142, 146), which can be called “Mendel’s theory of the development/evolution of hybrids” (DEH), and a theory that moves on a more “theoretical” level, according to Schleiden’s second “special guiding maxim”, the “Maxim of the autonomy of cells in plants” (SCHLEIDEN 1849: 146, 148), which can be called “Mendel’s theory of the cellular foundation of the development/evolution of hybrids” (CFH). The paper aims to present an analysis of these two theories and their intertheoretical relationships, carried out within the framework of the so-called Metatheoretical Structuralism (BALZER, MOULINES & SNEED 1987).
Fil: Lorenzano, Pablo Julio. Universidad Nacional de Quilmes. Departamento de Ciencias Sociales. Instituto de Estudios sobre la Ciencia y la Tecnología. Centro de Estudios de Filosofía e Historia de la Ciencia; Argentina. Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Científicas y Técnicas; Argentina - Materia
-
MENDEL
HYBRIDIST THEORIES
INTERTHEORETICAL RELATIONSHIPS
METATHEORETICAL STRUCTURALISM - Nivel de accesibilidad
- acceso abierto
- Condiciones de uso
- https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/2.5/ar/
- Repositorio
- Institución
- Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Científicas y Técnicas
- OAI Identificador
- oai:ri.conicet.gov.ar:11336/200714
Ver los metadatos del registro completo
id |
CONICETDig_a4641949a2c3df0108bb66b4fc03e138 |
---|---|
oai_identifier_str |
oai:ri.conicet.gov.ar:11336/200714 |
network_acronym_str |
CONICETDig |
repository_id_str |
3498 |
network_name_str |
CONICET Digital (CONICET) |
spelling |
An Analysis of Mendel's Two Hybridist Theories and their Intertheoretical RelationshipsLorenzano, Pablo JulioMENDELHYBRIDIST THEORIESINTERTHEORETICAL RELATIONSHIPSMETATHEORETICAL STRUCTURALISMhttps://purl.org/becyt/ford/6.3https://purl.org/becyt/ford/6Based on a statistical analysis of his experiments, which was a novelty for the tradition of “horticulturalists” (or “plant breeders”) as well as for the tradition of “hybridists”, and seeking a “generally applicable law governing the formation and development of hybrids” (MENDEL 1865: 3), Mendel states “the law of development/evolution found for Pisum” (MENDEL 1865: 32). When he tries to provide the “foundation and explanation” (MENDEL 1865: 32) of the law of formation and development of hybrids, he does it in terms of the production and behavior of egg cells and pollen cells, and, ultimately, in terms of the nature and behavior of what he calls “elements” (MENDEL 1865: 41) or “cell elements” (MENDEL 1865: 42). Moreover, Mendel recognizes the existence not just of hybrids that behave like those of Pisum – i.e., of “variable hybrids” – but also of hybrids that “remain perfectly like the hybrid and continue constant in their offspring” (MENDEL 1865: 38) and “acquire the status of new species” (MENDEL 1865: 40) – i.e., of “constant hybrids” (MENDEL 1869: 27–28, 31). The law that would govern the behavior of constant hybrids would also find its foundation and explanation in terms of the nature and behavior of elements (or cell elements). Mendel’s hybridism consists of two theories: a theory that moves on a more “empirical” level, according to Schleiden’s first “special guiding maxim”, the “Maxim of the history of development/evolution” (SCHLEIDEN 1849: 141, 142, 146), which can be called “Mendel’s theory of the development/evolution of hybrids” (DEH), and a theory that moves on a more “theoretical” level, according to Schleiden’s second “special guiding maxim”, the “Maxim of the autonomy of cells in plants” (SCHLEIDEN 1849: 146, 148), which can be called “Mendel’s theory of the cellular foundation of the development/evolution of hybrids” (CFH). The paper aims to present an analysis of these two theories and their intertheoretical relationships, carried out within the framework of the so-called Metatheoretical Structuralism (BALZER, MOULINES & SNEED 1987).Fil: Lorenzano, Pablo Julio. Universidad Nacional de Quilmes. Departamento de Ciencias Sociales. Instituto de Estudios sobre la Ciencia y la Tecnología. Centro de Estudios de Filosofía e Historia de la Ciencia; Argentina. Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Científicas y Técnicas; ArgentinaMoravian Museum Brno2022-12info:eu-repo/semantics/articleinfo:eu-repo/semantics/publishedVersionhttp://purl.org/coar/resource_type/c_6501info:ar-repo/semantics/articuloapplication/pdfapplication/pdfhttp://hdl.handle.net/11336/200714Lorenzano, Pablo Julio; An Analysis of Mendel's Two Hybridist Theories and their Intertheoretical Relationships; Moravian Museum Brno; Folia Mendeliana; 58; 2; 12-2022; 45-720085-07480085-0748CONICET DigitalCONICETenginfo:eu-repo/semantics/openAccesshttps://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/2.5/ar/reponame:CONICET Digital (CONICET)instname:Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Científicas y Técnicas2025-09-10T13:04:36Zoai:ri.conicet.gov.ar:11336/200714instacron:CONICETInstitucionalhttp://ri.conicet.gov.ar/Organismo científico-tecnológicoNo correspondehttp://ri.conicet.gov.ar/oai/requestdasensio@conicet.gov.ar; lcarlino@conicet.gov.arArgentinaNo correspondeNo correspondeNo correspondeopendoar:34982025-09-10 13:04:37.16CONICET Digital (CONICET) - Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Científicas y Técnicasfalse |
dc.title.none.fl_str_mv |
An Analysis of Mendel's Two Hybridist Theories and their Intertheoretical Relationships |
title |
An Analysis of Mendel's Two Hybridist Theories and their Intertheoretical Relationships |
spellingShingle |
An Analysis of Mendel's Two Hybridist Theories and their Intertheoretical Relationships Lorenzano, Pablo Julio MENDEL HYBRIDIST THEORIES INTERTHEORETICAL RELATIONSHIPS METATHEORETICAL STRUCTURALISM |
title_short |
An Analysis of Mendel's Two Hybridist Theories and their Intertheoretical Relationships |
title_full |
An Analysis of Mendel's Two Hybridist Theories and their Intertheoretical Relationships |
title_fullStr |
An Analysis of Mendel's Two Hybridist Theories and their Intertheoretical Relationships |
title_full_unstemmed |
An Analysis of Mendel's Two Hybridist Theories and their Intertheoretical Relationships |
title_sort |
An Analysis of Mendel's Two Hybridist Theories and their Intertheoretical Relationships |
dc.creator.none.fl_str_mv |
Lorenzano, Pablo Julio |
author |
Lorenzano, Pablo Julio |
author_facet |
Lorenzano, Pablo Julio |
author_role |
author |
dc.subject.none.fl_str_mv |
MENDEL HYBRIDIST THEORIES INTERTHEORETICAL RELATIONSHIPS METATHEORETICAL STRUCTURALISM |
topic |
MENDEL HYBRIDIST THEORIES INTERTHEORETICAL RELATIONSHIPS METATHEORETICAL STRUCTURALISM |
purl_subject.fl_str_mv |
https://purl.org/becyt/ford/6.3 https://purl.org/becyt/ford/6 |
dc.description.none.fl_txt_mv |
Based on a statistical analysis of his experiments, which was a novelty for the tradition of “horticulturalists” (or “plant breeders”) as well as for the tradition of “hybridists”, and seeking a “generally applicable law governing the formation and development of hybrids” (MENDEL 1865: 3), Mendel states “the law of development/evolution found for Pisum” (MENDEL 1865: 32). When he tries to provide the “foundation and explanation” (MENDEL 1865: 32) of the law of formation and development of hybrids, he does it in terms of the production and behavior of egg cells and pollen cells, and, ultimately, in terms of the nature and behavior of what he calls “elements” (MENDEL 1865: 41) or “cell elements” (MENDEL 1865: 42). Moreover, Mendel recognizes the existence not just of hybrids that behave like those of Pisum – i.e., of “variable hybrids” – but also of hybrids that “remain perfectly like the hybrid and continue constant in their offspring” (MENDEL 1865: 38) and “acquire the status of new species” (MENDEL 1865: 40) – i.e., of “constant hybrids” (MENDEL 1869: 27–28, 31). The law that would govern the behavior of constant hybrids would also find its foundation and explanation in terms of the nature and behavior of elements (or cell elements). Mendel’s hybridism consists of two theories: a theory that moves on a more “empirical” level, according to Schleiden’s first “special guiding maxim”, the “Maxim of the history of development/evolution” (SCHLEIDEN 1849: 141, 142, 146), which can be called “Mendel’s theory of the development/evolution of hybrids” (DEH), and a theory that moves on a more “theoretical” level, according to Schleiden’s second “special guiding maxim”, the “Maxim of the autonomy of cells in plants” (SCHLEIDEN 1849: 146, 148), which can be called “Mendel’s theory of the cellular foundation of the development/evolution of hybrids” (CFH). The paper aims to present an analysis of these two theories and their intertheoretical relationships, carried out within the framework of the so-called Metatheoretical Structuralism (BALZER, MOULINES & SNEED 1987). Fil: Lorenzano, Pablo Julio. Universidad Nacional de Quilmes. Departamento de Ciencias Sociales. Instituto de Estudios sobre la Ciencia y la Tecnología. Centro de Estudios de Filosofía e Historia de la Ciencia; Argentina. Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Científicas y Técnicas; Argentina |
description |
Based on a statistical analysis of his experiments, which was a novelty for the tradition of “horticulturalists” (or “plant breeders”) as well as for the tradition of “hybridists”, and seeking a “generally applicable law governing the formation and development of hybrids” (MENDEL 1865: 3), Mendel states “the law of development/evolution found for Pisum” (MENDEL 1865: 32). When he tries to provide the “foundation and explanation” (MENDEL 1865: 32) of the law of formation and development of hybrids, he does it in terms of the production and behavior of egg cells and pollen cells, and, ultimately, in terms of the nature and behavior of what he calls “elements” (MENDEL 1865: 41) or “cell elements” (MENDEL 1865: 42). Moreover, Mendel recognizes the existence not just of hybrids that behave like those of Pisum – i.e., of “variable hybrids” – but also of hybrids that “remain perfectly like the hybrid and continue constant in their offspring” (MENDEL 1865: 38) and “acquire the status of new species” (MENDEL 1865: 40) – i.e., of “constant hybrids” (MENDEL 1869: 27–28, 31). The law that would govern the behavior of constant hybrids would also find its foundation and explanation in terms of the nature and behavior of elements (or cell elements). Mendel’s hybridism consists of two theories: a theory that moves on a more “empirical” level, according to Schleiden’s first “special guiding maxim”, the “Maxim of the history of development/evolution” (SCHLEIDEN 1849: 141, 142, 146), which can be called “Mendel’s theory of the development/evolution of hybrids” (DEH), and a theory that moves on a more “theoretical” level, according to Schleiden’s second “special guiding maxim”, the “Maxim of the autonomy of cells in plants” (SCHLEIDEN 1849: 146, 148), which can be called “Mendel’s theory of the cellular foundation of the development/evolution of hybrids” (CFH). The paper aims to present an analysis of these two theories and their intertheoretical relationships, carried out within the framework of the so-called Metatheoretical Structuralism (BALZER, MOULINES & SNEED 1987). |
publishDate |
2022 |
dc.date.none.fl_str_mv |
2022-12 |
dc.type.none.fl_str_mv |
info:eu-repo/semantics/article info:eu-repo/semantics/publishedVersion http://purl.org/coar/resource_type/c_6501 info:ar-repo/semantics/articulo |
format |
article |
status_str |
publishedVersion |
dc.identifier.none.fl_str_mv |
http://hdl.handle.net/11336/200714 Lorenzano, Pablo Julio; An Analysis of Mendel's Two Hybridist Theories and their Intertheoretical Relationships; Moravian Museum Brno; Folia Mendeliana; 58; 2; 12-2022; 45-72 0085-0748 0085-0748 CONICET Digital CONICET |
url |
http://hdl.handle.net/11336/200714 |
identifier_str_mv |
Lorenzano, Pablo Julio; An Analysis of Mendel's Two Hybridist Theories and their Intertheoretical Relationships; Moravian Museum Brno; Folia Mendeliana; 58; 2; 12-2022; 45-72 0085-0748 CONICET Digital CONICET |
dc.language.none.fl_str_mv |
eng |
language |
eng |
dc.rights.none.fl_str_mv |
info:eu-repo/semantics/openAccess https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/2.5/ar/ |
eu_rights_str_mv |
openAccess |
rights_invalid_str_mv |
https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/2.5/ar/ |
dc.format.none.fl_str_mv |
application/pdf application/pdf |
dc.publisher.none.fl_str_mv |
Moravian Museum Brno |
publisher.none.fl_str_mv |
Moravian Museum Brno |
dc.source.none.fl_str_mv |
reponame:CONICET Digital (CONICET) instname:Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Científicas y Técnicas |
reponame_str |
CONICET Digital (CONICET) |
collection |
CONICET Digital (CONICET) |
instname_str |
Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Científicas y Técnicas |
repository.name.fl_str_mv |
CONICET Digital (CONICET) - Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Científicas y Técnicas |
repository.mail.fl_str_mv |
dasensio@conicet.gov.ar; lcarlino@conicet.gov.ar |
_version_ |
1842980158703665152 |
score |
12.993085 |